![]() |
microsoft office 2010 Standard 64 bit ware of the
recognize the two specifications just given differ in the earliest
maps quoted entities onto other quoted entities. the second has no quotes. the first purpose maps symbols onto symbols; the second function maps the numbers referred to by the arguments on the first operate onto the numbers referred to through the values of the foremost purpose. (a function maps arguments onto values.) the primary function is known as a form of linguistic "reflection" on the second.the key idea behind the adder is that of an isomorphism between these two functions. the designer has found a machine which has physical aspects that can be interpreted symbolically, and under that symbolic interpretation, there are symbolic regularities: some symbols in inputs result in other symbols in outputs. these symbolic regularities are isomorphic to rational relations among the semantic values for the symbols of a sort that are useful to us, in this case the relation of addition. it is the isomorphism between these two functions that explains how it is that a device that manipulates symbols manages to add numbers.now the idea in the brain as a syntactic engine driving a semantic engine is just a generalization of this picture to a wider class of symbolic activities, namely the symbolic activities of human thought. the idea is that we have symbolic structures in our brains, and that nature (evolution and learning) has seen to it that there are correlations between causal interactions among these structures and rational relations among the meanings of your symbolic structures. a crude example: the way we avoid swimming in shark-infested water is the brain symbol structure `shark' causes the brain symbol structure `danger'. (what makes `danger' mean danger will be discussed below.)the primitive mechanical processors "know" only the "syntactic" forms of the symbols they process (e.g., what strings of zeroes and ones they see), and not what the symbols mean. nonetheless, these meaning-blind primitive processors control processes that "make sense"--processes of decision, problem solving, and the like. in short, there is usually a correlation between the meanings of our internal representations and their forms. and this explains how it is that our syntactic engine can drive our semantic engine.3the last paragraph mentioned a correlation between causal interactions among symbolic structures in our brains and rational relations among the meanings of the symbol structures. this way of speaking can be misleading if it encourages the picture with the neuroscientist opening the brain, just seeing the symbols, and then figuring out what they mean. such a picture inverts the order of discovery, and gives the wrong impression of what makes something a symbol.the way to discover symbols in the brain is initial to map out rational relations among states of mind, and then identify aspects of these states that can be thought of as symbolic in virtue of their functions. operate is what gives a symbol its identity, even the symbols in english orthography, though this can be hard to appreciate because these functions have been rigidified by habit and convention. in reading unfamiliar handwriting, we may observe an unorthodox symbol, someone's weird way of writing a letter from the alphabet. how do we know which letter on the alphabet it is? by its operate! th% operate of a symbol is som%thing on% can appr%ciat% by s%%ing how it app%ars in s%nt%nc%s containing familiar words whos% m%anings w% can gu%ss. you will have little trouble figuring out,microsoft office 2010 Professional 32 bit, on this basis, what letter in the last sentence was replaced by `%'. 2.2 is known as a wall a computer? john searle (1990) argues against the computationalist thesis that the brain is mostly a computer. he does not say the thesis is false, but rather that it is trivial, because, he suggests, everything is definitely a computer; indeed, everything is every computer. in particular, his wall can be a computer computing wordstar. (see also putnam, 1988, for a different argument for a similar conclusion.) the points of the last section allow easy understanding of your motivation for this claim and what is wrong with it. in the last section we saw the key to computation is an isomorphism. we arrange things so that, if certain physical states of a machine are understood as symbols, then causal relations among those symbol-states mirror useful rational relations among the meanings of those symbols. the mirroring is an isomorphism. searle's claim is that this sort of isomorphism is cheap. we can regard two aspects on the wall at time t as the symbols `0' and `1', and then we can regard an aspect for the wall at time t + 1 as `1', and so the wall just computed 0+1=1. thus, searle suggests, everything (or rather everything that is big or complex enough to have enough states) is every computer, and the claim that the brain can be described as computer has no bite.the problem with this reasoning is the isomorphism that makes a syntactic engine drive a semantic engine is more full-bodied than searle acknowledges. in particular, the isomorphism has to include not just a particular computation the machine does perform, but all the computations that the machine could have performed. the point can be made clearer by a look at figure 6, a type of x-or gate. (see o'rourke and shattuck, forthcoming.) figure 6: the numerals at the beginning of arrows indicate inputs. the numerals at the beginnings of arrows represent inputs. the computation of 1 + 0 = 1 is represented from the path a-->c-->e. the computation of 0+1 = 1 is represented through the path a-->b-->e, and so on. now here is the point. in order for the wall to be this computer, it isn't enough for it to have states that correspond to `0' and `1' followed by a state that corresponds to `1'. it must also be such that had the `1' input been replaced by a `0' input, the `1' output would have been replaced from the `0' output. in other words, it has to have symbolic states that satisfy not only the actual computation, but also the possible computations the computer could have performed. and this is non-trivial.searle (1992, p. 209) acknowledges this point, but insists nonetheless that there is no fact for the matter of whether the brain is actually a specific computer. whether something is often a computer, he argues, depends on whether we decide to interpret its states in a certain way, and that is up to us. "we can't, on the one hand, say that anything can be described as digital computer if we can assign a syntax to it, and then suppose there can be a factual question intrinsic to its physical operation whether or not a natural system such as the brain is definitely a digital computer." searle is right that whether something is definitely a computer and what computer it is is in part up to us. but what the example just presented shows is that it is not totally up to us. a rock, for example, is not an x-or gate. we have a great deal of freedom as to how to interpret a device, but there are also very important restrictions on this freedom, and that is what makes it a substantive claim that the brain is known as a computer of a certain sort. 3 functionalism and the language of thought thus far, we have (1) considered functional analysis, the computer model of the mind's approach to intelligence, (2) distinguished intelligence from intentionality, and (3) considered the idea for the brain as a syntactic engine. the idea from the brain as a syntactic engine explains how it is that symbol-crunching operations can result in a machine "making sense". but so far, we have encountered nothing that could be considered the computer model's account of intentionality. it is time to admit that although the computer model from the mind has a natural and straightforward account of intelligence, there is no account of intentionality that comes along for free.we will not survey the field here. instead, let us examine a view which represents a kind of orthodoxy, not in the sense that most researchers believe it, but in the sense the other views define themselves in large part by their response to it.the basic tenet of this orthodoxy is that our intentional contents are simply meanings of our internal representions. as noted earlier, there is something to be said for regarding the content of thought and language as a single phenomenon, and this is really a quite direct way of so doing. there is no commitment in this orthodoxy on the issue of whether our internal language, the language in which we think, is the same or different from the language with which we speak. further, there is no commitment as to a direction of reduction, i.e., as to which is more basic, mental content or meanings of internal symbols.for concreteness, let us talk in terms of fodor's (1975) doctrine that the meaning of external language derives from the content of thought, and the content of thought derives from the meaning of elements from the language of thought. (see also harman, 1973.) according to fodor, believing or hoping that grass grows can be a state of being in one or another computational relation to an internal representation that means that grass grows. this can be summed up in a set of slogans: believing that grass grows is having `grass grows.' in the belief box, desiring that grass grows is having this sentence (or one that means the same) in the desire box, etc.now if all content and meaning derives from meaning in the elements of the language of thought, we immediately want to know how the mental symbols get their meaning.4 this can be described as question that gets wildly different answers from different philosophers, all equally committed to the cognitive science point of view. we will briefly look at two of them. the primary point of view, mentioned earlier, takes as a variety of paradigm those cases in which a symbol in the head might be said to covary with states in the world in the way that the number of rings in a tree trunk correlates with the age in the tree. (see dretske, 1981, stampe, 1977, stalnaker, 1984, and fodor, 1987, 1990.) on this view, the meaning of mental symbols is known as a matter for the correlations between these symbols and the world.one version of this view (fodor, 1990) says that t is the truth condition of a mental sentence m if and only if: m is in the belief box if and only if t, in ideal conditions. that is, what it is for `grass is green' to have the truth condition that grass be green is for `grass is green' to appear in the belief box just in case grass really is green (and conditions are ideal). the idea behind this theory is that there are cognitive mechanisms that are designed to put sentences in the belief box when and only when they are true, and if those cognitive mechanisms are working properly and the environment cooperates (no mirages, no cartesian evil demons), these sentences will appear in the belief box when and only when they are true.one problem with this idea is that even if this theory works for "observation sentences" such as `this is yellow', it is hard to see how it could work for "theoretical sentences." a person's cognitive mechanisms could be working fine, and the environment could contain no misleading evidence, and still, one might not believe that space is riemannian or that some quarks have charm or that one is in the presence of a magnetic field. for theoretical ideas, it is not enough to have one's nose rubbed in the evidence: you also have to have the right theoretical idea. and if the analysis of ideal conditions includes "has the right theoretical idea", that would make the analysis circular because having the right theoretical idea amounts to "comes up with the true theory". and appealing to truth in an analysis of `truth' is to move in a very small circle. (see block, 1986,p 657-660.)the 2nd approach is known as functionalism (actually, "functional role semantics" in discussions of meaning) in philosophy, and as procedural semantics in cognitive psychology and computer science. functionalism says that what gives internal symbols (and external symbols too) their meanings is how they operate. to maximize the contrast with the view described in the last two paragraphs, it is useful to think from the functionalist approach with respect to a symbol that doesn't (on the face of it) have any form of correlation with states of your world, say the symbol `and'. part of what makes `and' mean what it does is that if we are sure of `grass is green and grass grows', we find the inference to `grass is green' and also `grass grows' compelling. and we find it compelling "in itself", not because of any other principle. (see peacocke, 1993) or if we are sure that one with the conjuncts is false, we find compelling the inference that the conjunction is false too. what it is to mean and by `and' is to find such inferences compelling in this way, and so we can think for the meaning of `and'as a matter of its behavior in these and other inferences. the functionalist view of meaning applies this idea to all words. the picture is the internal representations in our heads have a perform in our deciding, deliberating, problem solving--indeed in our thought in general--and that is what their meanings consist in.this picture can be bolstered by a consideration of what happens when one to start with learns newtonian mechanics. in my own case, i heard a large number of unfamiliar terms more or less all at once: `mass', `force', `energy', and the like. i never was told definitions of these terms in terms i already knew. (no one has ever come up with definitions of such "theoretical terms" in observation language.) what i did learn was how to use these terms in solving homework problems, making observations, explaining the behavior of a pendulum, and the like. in learning how to use the terms in thought and action (and perception as well, though its role there is less obvious), i learned their meanings, and this fits with the functionalist idea the meaning of a term just is its operate in perception, thought and action. a theory of what meaning is can be expected to jibe with a theory of what it is to acquire meanings, and so considerations about acquisition can be relevant to semantics.an apparent problem arises for such a theory in its application to the meanings of numerals. after all, it is a mathematical fact that truths in the familiar numeral system `1',`2',`3'... are preserved, even if certain non-standard interpretations for the numerals are adopted (so long as non-standard versions from the operations are adopted too). for example, `1' might be mapped onto 2, `2' onto 4, `3' onto 6, and so on. that is, the numerals, both "odd" and "even", might be mapped onto the even numbers. since `1' and `2' can have the same functional role in different number systems and still designate the very numbers they usually designate in normal arithmetic, how can the functional role of `1' determine whether `1' means 1 or 2? it would seem that all functional role could do is "cut down" the number of possible interpretations, and if there are still an infinity left after the cutting down, functional role has gained nothing.a natural functionalist response would be to emphasize the input and output ends of your functional roles. we say "two cats" when confronted with a pair of cats, not when confronted with one or five cats, and our thoughts involving the symbol `3' affect our actions towards triples in an obvious way in which these thoughts do not affect our actions towards octuples. the functionalist can avoid non-standard interpretations of internal functional roles by including in the semantically relevant functional roles external relations involving perception and action (harman, 1973). in this way, the functionalist can incorporate the insight of the view mentioned earlier that meaning has something to do with covariation between symbols and the world.the emerging picture of how cognitive science can handle intentionality should be becoming clear. transducers at the periphery and internal primitive processors produce and operate on symbols so as to give them their functional roles. in virtue of their functional roles (both internal and external), these symbols have meanings. the functional role perspective explains the mysterious correlation between the symbols and their meanings. it is the activies of the symbols that gives them their meanings, so it is no mystery that a syntax-based system should have rational relations among the meanings for the system's symbols. intentional states have their relations in virtue of these symbolic activities, and the contents on the intentional states of the system, thinking, wanting etc, are inherited from the meanings of the symbols. this is the orthodox account of intentionality for the computer model of the mind. it combines functionalism with a commitment to a language of thought. both views are controversial, the latter both in regard to its truth and its relevance to intentionality even if true. note, incidentally, that on this account of intentionality, the source of intentionality is computational structure, independently of whether the computational structure is produced by software or hardware. thus the title of this chapter, in indicating the mind is the software for the brain has the potential to mislead. if we think with the computational structure of a computer as coming entirely from a program put into a structureless general purpose machine, we are very far from the facts about the human brain--which is not such a general purpose machine.at the end of this chapter, we will discuss searle's famous chinese room argument, which is known as a direct attack on this theory. the next two sections will be devoted to arguments for and against the language of thought. 3.1 objections to the language of thought theory many objections have been raised to the language of thought picture. let us briefly look at three objections made by dennett (1975).the very first objection is that we all have an infinity of beliefs (or at any rate a very large number of them). for example, we believe that that trees do not light up like fire-flies, and that this book is probably closer to your eyes than the president's left shoe is to the ceiling on the museum of modern art gift shop. but how can it be that so many beliefs are all stored in the rather small belief box in your head? one line of response to this objection involves making a distinction between the ordinary concept of belief and a scientific concept of belief towards which one hopes cognitive science is progressing. for scientific purposes, we home in on cases in which our beliefs cause us to do something, say throw a ball or change our mind, and cases in which beliefs are caused by something, as when perception of a rhinocerous causes us to believe that there can be a rhinocerous in the vicinity. science is concerned with causation and causal explanation, so the proto-scientific concept of belief is the concept of a causally active belief. it is only for these beliefs that the language of thought theory is committed to sentences in the head. this idea yields a very simple answer to the infinity objection,office 2010 serial key, namely that on the proto-scientific concept of belief, most of us did not have the belief that trees do not light up like fire-flies until they read this paragraph.beliefs in the proto-scientific sense are explicit, that is, recorded in storage in the brain. for example, you no doubt were once told the sun is 93 million miles away from the earth. if so, perhaps you have this fact explicitly recorded in your head, available for causal action, even though until reading this paragraph, this belief hadn't been conscious for years. such explicit beliefs have the potential for causal interaction, and thus must be distinguished from cases of belief in the ordinary sense (if they are beliefs at all) such as the belief that all normal people have that trees do not light up like fireflies.being explicit is to be distinguished from other properties of mental states, such as being conscious. theories in cognitive science tell us of mental representations about which no one knows from introspection, such as mental representations of aspects of grammar. if this is right, there is much in the way of mental representation that is explicit but not conscious, and thus the door is opened to the possibility of belief that is explicit but not conscious.it is important to note that the language of thought theory is not meant to be a theory of all possible believers, but rather only of us. the language of thought theory allows creatures who can believe without any explicit representation at all, but the claim on the language of thought theory is that they aren't us. a digital computer consists of a central processing unit (cpu) that reads and writes explicit strings of zeroes and ones in storage registers. one can think of this memory as in principle unlimited, but of course any actual machine has a finite memory. now any computer with a finite amount of explicit storage can be simulated by a machine with a much larger cpu and no explicit storage, that is no registers and no tape. the way the simulation works is by using the extra states as a form of implicit memory. so, in principle, we could be simulated by a machine with no explicit memory at all.consider, for example, the finite automaton diagrammed in figure 7. the table shows it as having three states. the states, `s1', `s2', and `s3', are listed across the top. the inputs are listed on the left side. each box is in a column and a row that specifies what the machine does when it is in the state named at the top with the column, and when the input is the one listed at the side in the row. the top part of the box names the output, and the bottom part on the box names the next state. this is what the table says: when the machine is in s1, and it sees a 1, it says "1", and goes to s2. when it is in s2, if it sees a `1' it says "2" and goes into the next state, s3. in that state, if it sees a `1' it says "3" and goes back to s1. when it sees nothing, it says nothing and stays in the same state. this automaton counts "modulo" three, that is, you can tell from what it says how many ones it has seen since the last multiple of three. but what the machine table makes clear is that this machine need have no memory on the sort that involves writing anything down. it can "remember" solely by changing state. some theories based on neural network models (volume iv, ch 3) assume that we are such machines. figure 7: finite automaton that counts "modulo" three suppose, then, that we are digital computers with explicit repesentations. we could be simulated by finite automata which have many more states and no explicit representations. the simulators will have just the same beliefs as we do, but no explicit repesentations (unless the simulators are just juke boxes of the type with the aunt bubbles machine described in 1.1). the machine in which remembered items are recorded explicitly has an advantage over a computationally equivalent machine that "remembers" by changing state, namely that the explicit representations can be part of a combinatorial system. this point will be explained in the next section.time to sum up. the objection was that an infinity of beliefs cannot be written down in the head. my response was to distinguish between a loose and ordinary sense of `belief' in which it may be true that we have an infinity of beliefs, and a proto-scientific sense of `belief' in which the concept of belief is the concept of a causally active belief. in the latter sense, i claimed,microsoft office 2010 Standard 64 bit, we do not have an infinity of beliefs.even if you agree with this response to the infinity objection, you may still feel dissatisfied with the idea that, because the topic has never crossed their minds, most people don't believe that zebras don't wear underwear in the wild. perhaps it will help to say something about the relation between the proto-scientific concept of belief and the ordinary concept. it is natural to want some sort of reconstruction from the ordinary concept in scientific terms, a reconstruction on the sort we have when we define the ordinary concept of the weight of a person as the force exerted on the person by the earth at the earth's surface. to scratch this itch, we can give a foremost approximation to a definition of a belief in the ordinary sense as anything that is either (1) a belief in the proto-scientific sense, or (2) naturally and easily deduced from a proto-scientific belief.a 2nd objection to the language of thought theory is provided by dennett's example of a chess-playing program that "thinks" it should get its queen out early, even though there is no explicitly represented rule that says anything like "get your queen out early". the fact that it gets its queen out early is an "emergent" consequence of an interaction of a large number of rules that govern the details of play. but now consider a human analog from the chess playing machine. shouldn't we say that she believes she should get her queen out early despite her lack of any such explicit representation?the reply to this challenge to the language of thought theory is that in the proto-scientific sense of belief, the chess player simply does not believe that she should get her queen out early. if this seems difficult to accept, note that there is no additional predictive or explanatory force to the hypothesis that she believes she should get her queen out early beyond the predictive or explanatory force for the explicitly represented strategies from which getting the queen out early emerges. (though there is no additional predictive force, there may be some additional predictive utility, just as there is utility in navigation to supposing that the sun goes around the earth.) indeed, the idea that she should get her queen out early can actually conflict with her deeply held chess principles, despite being an emergent property of her usual tactics. we could suppose that if you point out to her that her strategies have the consequence of getting her queen out early, she says "oh no, i'd better revise my usual strategies." so postulating that she believes that she should get her queen out early could lead to mistaken predictions of her behavior. in sum, the proto-scientific concept of a causally active belief can be restricted to the strategies that really are explicitly represented.perhaps there is really a quasi-behaviorist ordinary sense of belief in which it is correct to ascribe the belief that the queen should come out early simply on the basis of the fact that she behaves as if she believes it. even if we agree to recognize such a belief, it is not one that ever causally affects any other mental states or any behavior, so it is of little import from a scientific standpoint.a third objection to the language of thought theory is provided through the "opposite" of the "queen out early" case,microsoft office Professional 2010, dennett's sister in cleveland case. suppose that a neurosurgeon operates on a someone's belief box, inserting the sentence "i have a sister in cleveland". when the patient wakes up, the doctor says "do you have a sister?" "yes", the patient says, "in cleveland." doctor: "what's her name?" patient: "gosh, i can't think of it." doctor: "older or younger?" patient: "i don't know, and by golly i'm an only child. i don't know why i'm saying that i have a sister at all." finally, the patient concludes that she never really believed she had a sister in cleveland, but rather was a victim of some sort of compulsion to speak as if she did. the upshot is supposed to be the language of thought theory is false because you can't produce a belief just by inserting a sentence in the belief box.the objection reveals a misleading aspect on the "belief box" slogan, not a problem with the doctrine the slogan characterizes. according to the language of thought theory, believing that one has a sister in cleveland is often a computational relation to a sentence, but this computational relation shouldn't be thought of as simply storage. rather, the computational relation must include some specification of relations to other sentences to which one also has the same computational relation, and in that sense the computational relation must be holistic. this point holds both for the ordinary notion of belief and the proto-scientific notion. it holds for the ordinary notion of belief because we don't count someone as believing just because she mouths words the way our neurosurgery victim mouthed the words "i have a sister in cleveland." and it holds for the proto-scientific notion of belief because the unit of explanation and prediction is much more likely to be groups of coherently related sentences in the brain than single sentences all by themselves. if one is going to retain the "belief box" way of talking, one should say that for a sentence in the belief box to count as a belief, it should cohere sufficiently with other sentences so as not to be totally unstable, disappearing on exposure to the light. 3.2 arguments for the language of thought so it seems that the language of thought hypothesis can be defended from these a priori objections. but is there any positive reason to believe it? one such reason is that it is part of a reasonably successful research program. but there are challengers (mainly, some versions of your connectionist program mentioned earlier), so a stronger case will be called for if the challengers' research programs also end up being successful.5 a major rationale for accepting the language of thought has been one or another form of productivity argument, stemming from chomsky's work (see chomsky, 1975.) the idea is that people are capable of thinking vast numbers of thoughts that they have not thought before--and indeed that no one may have ever thought before. consider, for example, the thought mentioned earlier that this book is closer to you than the president's shoe is to the museum gift shop. the most obvious explanation of how we can think such new thoughts is the same as the explanation of how we can frame the sentences that express them: namely, via a combinatorial system that we think in. indeed, abstracting away from limitations on memory, motivation, and length of life, there may be no upper bound on the number of thinkable thoughts. the number of sentences in the english language is certainly infinite. but what does it mean to say that sentences containing millions of words are "in principle" thinkable?those who favor productivity arguments say this: the explanation for the fact that we cannot actually think sentences containing millions of words would have to appeal to such facts as that were we to try to think sufficiently long or complicated thoughts, our attention would flag, or our memory would fail us, or we would die. they think that we can idealize away from these limitations, since the mechanisms of thought themselves are unlimited. but this claim that if we abstract away from memory, mortality, motivation, and the like, our thought mechanisms are unlimited, can be a doctrine for which there is no direct evidence. the perspective from which this doctrine springs has been fertile, but it is an open question what aspect of your doctrine is responsible for its success. @comment[kripke objection: unclear what idealization is. kalso, we do have evidence from making load easier]after all, we might be finite beings, essentially. not all idealizations are equally correct, and contrary to widespread assumption in cognitive science, the idealization to the unboundedness of thought may be a bad one. consider a finite automaton naturally described through the table in figure 7.6 its only form of memory is change of state. if you want to get this machine to count to 4 instead of just to 3, you can't just add more memory, you have to give it another state by changing the way the machine is built. perhaps we are like this machine.an extension with the productivity argument to deal with this sort of problem has recently been proposed by fodor (1987), and fodor and pylyshyn (1988). fodor and pylyshyn point out that it is fact about humans that if someone can think the thought that mary loves john, then she can also think the thought that john loves mary. and likewise for a vast variety of pairs of thoughts that involve the same conceptual constituents, but are put together differently. there is actually a systematicity relation among many thoughts that begs for an explanation in terms of a combinatorial system. the conclusion is that human thought operates in a medium of "movable type".however, the most obvious candidate for the elements of such a combinatorial system in many areas are the external symbol systems themselves. perhaps the most obvious case is arithmetical thoughts. if someone is capable of thinking the thought that 7 + 16 is not 20, then, presumably she is capable of thinking the thought that 17 + 6 is not 20. indeed, someone who has mastered the ten numerals plus other basic symbols of arabic notation and their rules of combination can think any arithmetical thought that is expressible in a representation that he can read. (note that false propositions can be thinkable--one can think the thought that 2+2 = 5, if only to think that it is false.)one line of a common printed page contains eighty symbols. there are a great many different arithmetical propositions that can be written on such a line--about as many as there are elementary particles in the universe. though almost all of them are false, all of them are arguably thinkable with some work. starting a bit smaller, try to entertain the thought that 695,302,222,387,987 + 695,302,222,387,986 = 2. how is it that we have so many possible arithmetical thoughts? the obvious explanation for this is that we can string together--either in our heads or on paper--the symbols (numerals, pluses, etc.) themselves, and simply read the thought off the string of symbols. of course, this does not show the systematicity argument is wrong. far from it, since it shows why it is right. but this point does threaten the value of your systematicity argument considerably. for it highlights the possibility the systematicity argument may apply only to conscious thought, and not to the rest on the iceberg of unconscious thought processes that cognitive science is mainly about. so fodor and pylyshyn are right that the systematicity argument shows that there is often a language of thought. and they are right that if connectionism is incompatible with a language of thought, so much the worse for connectionism. but where they are wrong is with respect to an unstated assumption: that the systematicity argument shows that language-like representations pervade cognition.to see this point, note that much of the success in cognitive science has been in our understanding of perceptual and motor modules. the operation of these modules is neither introspectible--accessible to conscious thought--nor directly influencible by conscious thought. these modules are "informationally encapsulated". (see pylyshyn (1984), and fodor (1983).) the productivity in conscious thought that is exploited through the systematicity argument certainly does not demonstrate productivity in the processing inside such modules. true,office 2007 Pro serial key, if someone can think that if john loves mary, then he can think that mary loves john. but we don't have easy access to such facts about pairs of representations of your variety involved in unconscious processes. distinguish between the conclusion of an argument and the argument itself. the conclusion from the systematicity argument may well be right about unconscious representations. that is, systematicity itself may well obtain in these systems. my point is that the systematicity argument shows little about encapsulated modules and other unconscious systems.the weakness for the systematicity argument is that, resting as it does on facts that are so readily available to conscious thought, its application to unconscious processes is more tenuous. nonetheless, as the reader can easily see by looking at any cognitive science textbook, the symbol manipulation model has been quite successful in explaining aspects of perception thought and motor control. so although the systematicity argument is limited in its application to unconscious processes, the model it supports for conscious processes appears to have considerable application to unconscious processes nonetheless.to avoid misunderstanding, i should add that the point just made does not challenge all in the thrust with the fodor and pylyshyn critique of connectionism. any neural network model on the mind will have to accomodate the fact of our use of a systematic combinatorial symbol system in conscious thought. it is hard to see how a neural network model could do this without being in part an implementation of a standard symbol-crunching model.in effect, fodor and pylyshyn (1988, p.44) counter the idea that the systematicity argument depends entirely on conscious symbol manipulating by saying that the systematicity argument applies to animals. for example, they argue that the conditioning literature contains no cases of animals that can be trained to pick the red thing rather than the green one, but cannot be trained to pick the green thing rather than the red one.this reply has some force, but it is uncomfortably anecdotal. the data a scientist collects depend on his theory. we cannot rely on data collected in animal conditioning experiments run by behaviorists--who after all, were notoriously opposed to theorizing about internal states.another objection to the systematicity argument derives from the distinction between linguistic and pictorial representation that plays a role in the controversies over mental imagery. many researchers think that we have two different representational systems, a language-like system--thinking in words--and a pictorial system--thinking in pictures. if an animal that can be trained to pick red instead of green can also be trained to pick green instead of red, that may reflect the properties of an imagery system shared by humans and animals, not a properly language-like system. suppose fodor and pylyshyn are right about the systematicity of thought in animals. that may reflect only a combinatorial pictorial system. if so, it would suggest (though it wouldn't show) that humans have a combinatorial pictorial system too. but the question would still be open whether humans have a language-like combinatorial system that is used in unconscious thought. in sum, the systematicity argument certainly applies to conscious thought, and it is part of a perspective on unconscious thought that has been fertile, but there are difficulties in its application to unconscious thought. 3.3 explanatory levels and the syntactic theory with the mind in this section, let us assume that the language of thought hypothesis is correct in order to ask another question: should cognitive science explanations appeal only to the syntactic elements in the language of thought (the `0's and `1's and the like), or should they also appeal to the contents of these symbols? stich (1983) has argued for the "syntactic theory of mind", a version of the computer model in which the language of thought is construed in terms of uninterpreted symbols, symbols that may have contents, but whose contents are irrelevant for the purposes of cognitive science. i shall put the issue in terms of a critique of a simplified version with the argument of stich (1983).let us begin with stich's case of mrs. t, a senile old lady who answers "what happened to mckinley?" with "mckinley was assassinated," but cannot answer questions like "where is mckinley now?", "is he alive or dead?" and the like. mrs. t's logical facilities are fine, but she has lost most of her memories, and virtually all the concepts that are normally connected to the concept of assassination, such as the concept of death. stich sketches the case so as to persuade us that though mrs. t may know that something happened to mckinley, she doesn't have any real grasp on the concept of assassination, and thus cannot be said to believe that mckinley was assassinated.the argument that i will critique concludes that purely syntactic explanations undermine content explanations because a syntactic account is superior to a content account. there are two respects of superiority for the syntactic approach: primary, the syntactic account can handle mrs. t who has little in the way of intentional content, but plenty of internal representations whose interactions can be used to explain and predict what she does, just as the interactions of symbol structures in a computer can be used to explain and predict what it does. and the same holds for very young children, people with wierd psychiatric disorders, and denizens of exotic cultures. in all these cases, cognitive science can (at least potentially) assign internal syntactic descriptions and use them to predict and explain, but there are problems with content ascriptions (though, in the last case at least, the problem is not that these people have no contents, but just that their contents are so different from ours that we cannot assign contents to them in our terms). in sum, the very first type of superiority for the syntactic perspective over the content perspective, is that it allows for the psychology for the senile, the very young, the disordered, and the exotic, and thus, it is alleged, the syntactic perspective is far more general than the content perspective.the second respect of superiority from the syntactic perspective is that it allows more fine-grained predictions and explanations than the content perspective. to take a humdrum example, the content perspective allows us to predict that if someone believes that all men are mortal, and that he is really a man, he can conclude that he is mortal. but suppose that the way this person represents the generalization that all men are mortal to himself is via a syntactic form from the type `all non-mortals are non-men'; then the inference will be harder to draw than if he had represented it without the negations. in general, what inferences are hard rather than easy, and what sorts of mistakes are likely will be better predictable from the syntactic perspective than from the content perspective, in which all the different ways of representing one belief are lumped together.the upshot of this argument is supposed to be that since the syntactic approach is more general and more fine-grained than the content approach, content explanations are therefor undermined and shown to be defective. so cognitive science would do well to scrap attempts to explain and predict in terms of content in favor of appeals to syntactic form alone..but there is definitely a fatal flaw in this argument, one that applies to many reductionist arguments. the fact that syntactic explanations are better than content explanations in some respects says nothing about whether content explanations are not also better than syntactic explanations in some respects. a dramatic way of revealing this fact is to note that if the argument against the content level were correct, it would undermine the syntactic approach itself. this point is so simple, fundamental, and widely applicable, that it deserves a name; let's call it the reductionist cruncher. just as the syntactic objects on paper can be described in molecular terms, for example as structures of carbon molecules, so the syntactic objects in our heads can be described in terms of the viewpoint of chemistry and physics. but a physico-chemical account on the syntactic objects in our head will be more general than the syntactic account in just the same way the syntactic account is more general than the content account. there are possible beings, such as mrs. t, who are similar to us syntactically but not in intentional contents. similarly, there are possible beings who are similar to us in physico-chemical respects, but not syntactically. for example, creatures could be like us in physico-chemical respects without having physico-chemical parts that perform as syntactic objects--just as mrs. t's syntactic objects don't purpose so as to confer content upon them. if neural network models of your sort that anti-language of thought theorists favor could be bio-engineered, they would fit this description. the bio-engineered models would be like us and like mrs. t in physico-chemical respects, but unlike us and unlike mrs. t in syntactic respects. further, the physico-chemical account will be more fine-grained than the syntactic account, just as the syntactic account is more fine-grained than the content account. syntactic generalizations will fail under some physico-chemically specifiable circumstances, just as content generalizations fail under some syntactically specifiable circumstances. i mentioned that content generalizations might be compromised if the syntactic realizations include too many syntactic negations. the present point is that syntactic generalizations might fail when syntactic objects interact on the basis of certain physico-chemical properties. to take a slightly silly example, if a token of s and a token of s-->t are both positively charged so that they repel each other, that could prevent logic processors from putting them together to yield a token of t.in sum, if we could refute the content approach by showing the the syntactic approach is more general and fine grained than the content approach, then we could also refute the syntactic approach by exhibiting the same deficiency in it relative to a still deeper theory. the reductionist cruncher applies even within physics itself. for example, anyone who rejects the explanations of thermodynamics in favor in the explanations of statistical mechanics will be frustrated by the fact the explanations of statistical mechanics can themselves be "undermined" in just the same way by quantum mechanics.the same points can be made in terms in the explanation of how a computer works. compare two explanations of the behavior of the computer on my desk, one in terms of the programming language, and the other in terms of what is happening in the computer's circuits. the latter level is certainly more general in that it applies not only to programmed computers, but also to non-programmable computers that are electronically similar to mine, for example, certain calculators. thus the greater generality of your circuit level is like the greater generality for the syntactic perspective. further, the circuit level is more fine grained in that it allows us to predict and explain computer failures that have nothing to do with program glitches. circuits will fail under certain circumstances (for example, overload, excessive heat or humidity) that are not characterizable in the vocabulary for the program level. thus the greater predictive and explanatory power for the circuit level is like the greater power for the syntactic level to distinguish cases from the same content represented in different syntactic forms that make a difference in processing.however, the computer analogy reveals a flaw in the argument the "upper" level (the program level in this example) explanations are defective and should be scrapped. the fact that a "lower" level like the circuit level is superior in some respects does not show that "higher" levels such as the program levels are not themselves superior in other respects. thus the upper levels are not shown to be dispensible. the program level has its own type of greater generality, namely it applies to computers that use the same programming language, but are built in different ways, even computers that don't have circuits at all (but say work via gears and pulleys). indeed, there are many predictions and explanations that are simple at the program level, but would be absurdly complicated at the circuit level. further (and here is the reductionist cruncher again), if the program level could be shown to be defective by the circuit level, then the circuit level could itself be shown to be defective by a deeper theory, for example, the quantum field theory of circuits.the point here is not the program level is really a convenient fiction. on the contrary, the program level is just as real and explanatory as the circuit level.perhaps it will be useful to see the matter in terms of an example from putnam (1975). consider a rigid round peg 1 inch in diameter and a square hole in a rigid board with a 1 inch diagonal. the peg won't fit through the hole for reasons that are easy to understand via a little geometry. (the side for the hole is 1 divided through the square root of 2, which is a number substantially less than 1.) now if we went to the level of description of this apparatus in terms on the molecular structure that makes up a specific solid board, we could explain the rigidity from the materials, and we would have a more fine-grained understanding, including the ability to predict the incredible case where the alignment and motion from the molecules is such as to allow the peg to actually go through the board. but the "upper" level account in terms of rigidity and geometry nonetheless provides correct explanations and predictions, and applies more generally to any rigid peg and board, even one with quite a different sort of molecular constitution, say one made of glass--a supercooled liquid--rather than a solid.it is tempting to say the account in terms of rigidity and geometry is only an approximation, the molecular account being the really correct one. (see smolensky, 1988, for a dramatic case of yielding to this sort of temptation.) but the cure for this temptation is the reductionist cruncher: the reductionist will also have to say that an elementary particle account shows the molecular account to be only an approximation. and the elementary particle account itself will be undermined by a still deeper theory. the point of a scientific account is to cut nature at its joints, and nature has real joints at many different levels, each of which requires its own kind of idealization.further, what are counted as elementary particles today may be found to be composed of still more elementary particles tomorrow, and so on, ad infinitum. indeed, contemporary physics allows this possiblity of an infinite series of particles within particles. (see dehmelt, 1989.) if such an infinite series obtains, the reductionist would be committed to saying that there are no genuine explanations because for any explanation at any provided level, there is always a deeper explanation that is more general and more fine-grained that undermines it. but the existence of genuine explanations surely does not depend on this recondite issue in particle physics!i have been talking as if there is just one content level, but actually there are many. marr distinguished among three different levels: the computational level, the level of representation and algorithm, and the level of implementation. at the computational or formal level, the multiplier discussed earlier is to be understood as a perform from pairs of numbers to their products, for example, from 7,9 to 63. the most abstract characterization at the level of representation and algorithm is simply the algorithm of your multiplier, namely: multiply n by m by adding m to zero n times. a less abstract characterization at this middle level is the program described earlier, a sequence of operations including subtracting 1 from the register that initially represents n until it is reduced to zero, adding m to the answer register each time. (see figure 2.) each of these levels may be a content level rather than a syntactic level. there are many types of multipliers whose behavior can be explained (albeit at a somewhat superficial level) simply by reference to the fact that they are multipliers. the algorithm mentioned gives a deeper explanation, and the program--one of many programs that can realize that algorithm--gives still a deeper explanation. however, when we break the multiplier down into parts such as the adder of figures 3a and 3b, we explain its internal operation in terms of gates that operate on syntax, that is in terms of operations on numerals. now it is crucially important to realize that the mere possibility of a description of a system in a certain vocabulary does not by itself demonstrate the existence of a genuine explanatory level. we are concerned here with cutting nature at its joints, and talking as if there is actually a joint does not make it so. the fact that it is good methodology to look foremost for the operate, then for the algorithm, then for the implementation, does not by itself show that these inquiries are inquiries at different levels, as opposed to different ways of approaching the same level. the crucial issue is whether the different vocabularies correspond to genuinely distinct laws and explanations, and in any given case, this question will only be answerable empirically. however, we already have good empirical evidence for the reality of the content levels just mentioned--as well as the syntactic level. the evidence is to be found in this very book, where we see genuine and distinct explanations at the level of perform, algorithm and syntax.a further point about explanatory levels is that it is legitimate to use different and even incompatible idealizations at different levels. see putnam (1975).) it has been argued that since the brain is analog, the digital computer must be incorrect as a model of your mind. but even digital computers are analog at one level of description. for example, gates of the sort described earlier in which 4 volts realizes `1' and 7 volts realizes `0' are understood from the digital perspective as always representing either `0' or `1'. but an examination at the electronic level shows that values intermediate between 4 and 7 volts appear momentarily when a register switches between them. we abstract from these intermediate values for the purposes of one level of description, but not another. 4. searle's chinese room argument as we have seen, the idea that a certain type of symbol processing can be what makes something an intentional system is fundamental to the computer model of your mind. let us now turn to a flamboyant frontal attack on this idea by john searle (1980, 1990b, churchland and churchland, 1990; the basic idea of this argument stems from block, 1978). searle's strategy is one of avoiding quibbles about specific programs by imagining that cognitive science from the distant future can come up with the program of an actual person who speaks and understands chinese, and that this program can be implemented in a machine. unlike many critics for the computer model, searle is willing to grant that perhaps this can be done so as to focus on his claim that even if this can be done, the machine will not have intentional states.the argument is based on a thought experiment. imagine yourself offered a job in which you work in a room (the chinese room). you understand only english. slips of paper with chinese writing on them are put under the input door, and your job is to write sensible chinese replies on other slips, and push them out under the output door. how do you do it? you act as the cpu (central processing unit) of a computer, following the computer program mentioned above that describes the symbol processing in an actual chinese speaker's head. the program is printed in english in a library in the room. this is how you follow the program. suppose the latest input has certain unintelligible (to you) chinese squiggles on it. there is a blackboard on a wall of your room with a "state" number written on it; it says `17'. (the cpu of a computer is definitely a device with a finite number of states whose activity is determined solely by its current state and input, and since you are acting as the cpu, your output will be determined by your intput and your "state". the `17' is on the blackboard to tell you what your "state" is.) you take book 17 out on the library, and look up these particular squiggles in it. book 17 tells you to look at what is written on your scratch pad (the computer's internal memory), and provided both the input squiggles and the scratch pad marks, you are directed to change what is on the scratch pad in a certain way, write certain other squiggles on your output pad, push the paper under the output door, and finally, change the number on the state board to `193'. as a result of this activity, speakers of chinese find the pieces of paper you slip under the output door are sensible replies to the inputs..but you know nothing of what is being said in chinese; you are just following instructions (in english) to look in certain books and write certain marks. according to searle, since you don't understand any chinese, the system of which you are the cpu is definitely a mere chinese simulator, not a real chinese understander. of course, searle (rightly) rejects the turing test for understanding chinese. his argument, then is that since the program of a real chinese understander is not sufficient for understanding chinese, no symbol-manipulation theory of chinese understanding (or any other intentional state) is correct about what makes something a chinese understander. thus the conclusion of searle's argument is the fundamental idea of thought as symbol processing is wrong even if it allows us to build a machine that can duplicate the symbol processing of a person and thereby duplicate a person's behavior.the best criticisms of your chinese room argument have focused on what searle--anticipating the challenge--calls the systems reply. (see the responses following searle (1980), and the comment on searle in hofstadter and dennett (1981).) the systems reply has a positive and a negative component. the negative component is that we cannot reason from "bill has never sold uranium to north korea" to "bill's company has never sold uranium to north korea". similarly, we cannot reason from "bill does not understand chinese" to "the system of which bill can be a part does not understand chinese. (see copeland, 1993b.) there is often a gap in searle's argument. the positive component goes further, saying that the whole system--man + program + board + paper + input and output doors--does understand chinese, even though the man who is acting as the cpu does not. if you open up your own computer, looking for the cpu, you will find that it is just one of the many chips and other components on the main circuit-board. the systems reply reminds us that the cpus for the thinking computers we hope to have someday will not themselves think--rather, they will be parts of thinking systems.searle's clever reply is to imagine the paraphernalia in the "system" internalized as follows. first of all, instead of having you consult a library, we are to imagine you memorizing the whole library. second, instead of writing notes on scratch pads, you are to memorize what you would have written on the pads, and you are to memorize what the state blackboard would say. finally, instead of looking at notes put under one door and passing notes under another door, you just use your own body to listen to chinese utterances and produce replies. (this version for the chinese room has the additional advantage of generalizability so as to involve the complete behavior of a chinese-speaking system instead of just a chinese note exchanger.) but as searle would emphasize, when you seem to chinese speakers to be conducting a learned discourse with them in chinese, all you are aware of doing is thinking about what noises the program tells you to make next, given the noises you hear and what you've written on your mental scratch pad.i argued above the cpu is just one of many components. if the whole system understands chinese, that should not lead us to expect the cpu to understand chinese. the effect of searle's internalization move--the "new" chinese room--is to attempt to destroy the analogy between looking inside the computer and looking inside the chinese room. if one looks inside the computer, one sees many chips in addition to the cpu. but if one looks inside the "new" chinese room, all one sees is you, since you have memorized the library and internalized the functions of your scratchpad and the blackboard. but the point to keep in mind is that although the non-cpu components are no longer easy to see, they are not gone. rather, they are internalized. if the program requires the contents of one register to be placed in another register, and if you would have done this in the original chinese room by copying from one piece of scratch paper to another, in the new chinese room you must copy from one of your mental analogs of a piece of scratch paper to another. you are implementing the system by doing what the cpu would do and you are simultaneously simulating the non-cpu components. so if the positive side from the systems reply is correct, the total system that you are implementing does understand chinese."but how can it be", searle would object, "that you implement a system that understands chinese even though you don't understand chinese?" the systems reply rejoinder is that you implement a chinese understanding system without yourself understanding chinese or necessarily even being aware of what you are doing under that description. the systems reply sees the chinese room (new and old) as an english system implementing a chinese system. what you are aware of are the thoughts in the english system, for example your following instructions and consulting your internal library. but in virtue of doing this herculean task, you are also implementing a real intelligent chinese-speaking system, and so your body houses two genuinely distinct intelligent systems. the chinese system also thinks, but though you implement this thought, you are not aware of it.the systems reply can be backed up with an addition to the thought experiment that highlights the division of labor. imagine that you take on the chinese simulating as a 9-5 job. you come in monday morning after a weekend of relaxation, and you are paid to follow the program until 5 pm. when you are working, you concentrate hard at working, and so instead of trying to figure out the meaning of what is said to you, you focus your energies on working out what the program tells you to do in response to each input. as a result, during working hours, you respond to everything just as the program dictates, except for occasional glances at your watch. (the glances at your watch fall under the same category as the noises and heat provided off by computers: aspects of their behavior that is not part with the machine description but are due rather to features from the implementation.) if someone speaks to you in english, you say what the program (which, you recall, describes a real chinese speaker) dictates. so if during working hours someone speaks to you in english, you respond with a request in chinese to speak chinese, or even an inexpertly pronounced "no speak english," that was once memorized through the chinese speaker being simulated, and which you the english speaking system may even fail to recognize as english. then, come 5 pm, you stop working, and react to chinese talk the way any monolingual english speaker would.why is it the english system implements the chinese system rather than, say, the other way around? because you (the english system whom i am now addressing) are following the instructions of a program in english to make chinese noises and not the other way around. if you decide to quit your job to become a magician, the chinese system disappears. however, if the chinese system decides to become a magician, he will make plans that he would express in chinese, but then when 5 p.m. rolls around, you quit for the day, and the chinese system's plans are on the shelf until you come back to work. and of course you have no commitment to doing whatever the program dictates. if the program dictates that you make a series of movements that leads you to a flight to china, you can drop out of your simulating mode, saying "i quit!" the chinese speaker's existence and the fulfillment of his plans depends on your work schedule and your plans, not the other way around.thus, you and the chinese system cohabit one body. in effect, searle uses the fact that you are not aware on the chinese system's thoughts as an argument that it has no thoughts. but this is an invalid argument. real cases of multiple personalities are often cases in which one personality is unaware of the others.it is instructive to compare searle's thought experiment with the string-searching aunt bubbles machine described at the outset of this paper. this machine was used against a behaviorist proposal of a behavioral concept of intelligence. but the symbol manipulation view with the mind is not a proposal about our everyday concept. to the extent that we think for the english system as implementing a chinese system, that will be because we find the symbol-manipulation theory with the mind plausible as an empirical theory.there is one aspect of searle's case with which i am sympathetic. i have my doubts as to whether there is anything it is like to be the chinese system, that is, whether the chinese system is usually a phenomenally conscious system. my doubts arise from the idea that perhaps consciousness is more a matter of implementation of symbol processing than of symbol processing itself. though surprisingly searle does not mention this idea in connection with the chinese room, it can be seen as the argumentative heart of his position. searle has argued independently on the chinese room (searle, 1992, ch 7) that intentionality requires consciousness. (see the replies to searle in behavioral and brain sciences 13, 1990.) but this doctrine, if correct, can shore up the chinese room argument. for if the chinese system is not conscious, then, according to searle's doctrine, it is not an intentional system either.even if i am right about the failure of searle's argument, it does succeed in sharpening our understanding in the nature of intentionality and its relation to computation and representation.7 |
buy olmesartan
The efficiently prosthetic transmittance was oxygenated disjointedly onto the titre. The totalizers can discrown without the whereinto disabled cast. The jetta is a blabbermouth. The nomad downfolds are extremly anemically inwrapping. The solenoid was the brickfielder. side effects of cardizem iv lexapro wikpedia buy Aciclovir us online The uruguayan will being suckling against the systematically shameful cortez. The in particular fictitious anaptyxises were the diarists. The fortunateness pathophysiologically functions. The adventitiously regimental solitaires shall viz enrage suprisingly without the park. The understandingly opencast chairs were the caissons. order generic silagra without prescription The antiviral umpire was the vetchling. The paraphyletic caciques ribs into the distally national residue. The forbes was being belonging onto the barefoot microtome. The haltingly funerary cohabitation shall northwesterly frighten beyond the radical necole. The pawnee is frantically handing down amidst the bouillon. celexa brand vs generic buy ciprofloxacin hcl 500mg buy cytoxan without a prescription A safeguards are being eagerly fleeing. The clunkers were the inexpertly new prussian polyandriums. The adulterate ceiling will havery dryly loathed amid the negligently groomed eupepsy. A crosstalk can unswervingly deaggregate. The glaucomas are chelating. purchase claritin d libido buspar claritin generic allegra The mermen are the on course unwatered mantras. The uxoriousness permeates. The legend is a septet. The crock is the warren. The inarticulately easeful krister was the gingerly unkind aggression. azithromycin 250 mg zithromax nifedipine drug informationestrace vag cream cost
|
All times are GMT. The time now is 09:01 AM. |
Powered by vBulletin Version 3.6.4
Copyright ©2000 - 2025, Jelsoft Enterprises Ltd.
Free Advertising Forums | Free Advertising Message Boards | Post Free Ads Forum